Higher Pleasures
Does Millâs distinction between higher and lower pleasures achieve what he wants it to achieve?
(January 2025): I think some of the symmetry discussion, like a lot of discussion of skepticism in general, is too dialectically-minded. People can know what the higher pleasures are, even if they canât convince their opponents. However, there might still be a problem of making the higher pleasures depend on peoplesâ judgments (âwhat makes one pleasure more valuable than anotherâ), rather than taking these judgments as merely indicating what the objectively higher pleasures are. Also, note that the transfinite ordinal scale isnât really needed (as with slightly less naive utility functions we can represent welfare levels with just the reals).
One worry for utilitarian theories of value is that they are degrading. Under simple hedonism:
(1) If two things yield the same quantity of pleasure, they are equally valuable.
But it seems plausible that:
(2) Push-pin yields the same quantity of pleasure as poetry.
So, simple hedonists commit themselves to Benthamâs position:
(3) âThe game of push-pin is of equal value with the arts and sciences of music and poetry.â
This degrading conclusion seems absurd enough to disqualify hedonism as a theory of value. In response, simple hedonists may deny (2). Poetry has âgreater permanency, safety, uncostliness, etc.â and thus yields far more pleasure than push-pin in the long term. But perhaps this defense is too contingent: that is, it might fail to defuse other objections in this family of worries.
With his distinction between higher and lower pleasures, Mill aims to provide a more principled defense of utilitarian theories of value. In particular, he aims to construct a more sophisticated1 theory of value which doesnât entail (1). On a faithful finitary reading of Millâs distinction, it fails to stand up to a more sophisticated degradingness objection (namely, Crispâs (Oyster) case). Thus, it fails to achieve a more principled defense. Crispâs infinitary reading is less faithful to Millâs writing, but it succeeds on (Oyster). The simple infinitary reading also stands up against Crispâs (Austerity) objection. However, Millâs distinction falls to a (Symmetry) objection adapted from Smart, whose own response is inadequate. So, Millâs distinction does not achieve what he wants it to achieve.
(In)finitary readings
Here is a long quotation where Mill motivates, as outlined above, his distinction:
Utilitarian writers in general have placed the superiority of mental over bodily pleasures chiefly inâŠtheir circumstantial advantages rather than in their intrinsic nature. And on all these points utilitarians have fully proved their case; but they might have taken the other, and, as it may be called, higher ground, with entire consistency. It is quite compatible with the principle of utility to recognise the fact, that some kinds of pleasure are more desirable and more valuable than others. It would be absurd that while, in estimating all other things, quality is considered as well as quantity, the estimation of pleasures should be supposed to depend on quantity alone.
Now, Millâs distinction may be interpreted finitarily: for any two pleasures and a quantity , there is some finite multiplier such that of the higher is worth of the lower. Alternatively, Mill may be interpreted infinitarily: for some pairs of pleasures there is no finite (i.e., a minimal amount of the higher pleasure is worth more than any finite amount of the lower pleasure).2 Millâs writing is more consistent with the finitary view (italics mine):
If one of the two [pleasures] is, by those who are competently acquainted with both, placed so far above the other that they prefer it, even though knowing it to be attended with a greater amount of discontent, and would not resign it for any quantity of the other pleasure which their nature is capable of, we are justified in ascribing to the preferred enjoyment a superiority in quality, so far out-weighing quantity as to render it, in comparison, of small account.
This seems to imply that although may be very large, it must be finite. In the first case, it might be limited by natural capacity (e.g., lifespan). In the second case, quantity is of small account rather than of no account, which would be implied by the infinitary view. However, Mill might have simply lacked the tools to articulate the infinitary view, and so this reading might just be anachronistic rather than totally inconsistent.
Oysters
The finitary reading does not fully achieve Millâs aim. After making his distinction, we have:
(1â) If two things yield the same quality-adjusted amount of pleasure, they are equally valuable.
The finitary reading falls to an amended version (Oyster) of the degradingness objection:
(2â) A magical oyster living years yields the same quality-adjusted amount of pleasure as Hadynâs life.
(3â) So, the oysterâs life is of equal value with Hadynâs life.
The finitary viewâs implication that a sufficiently long-lived oyster has a life as valuable as Hadynâs is seen as disqualifying. Since it falls to (Oyster), the finitary view fails Millâs goal of providing a more principled defense of utilitarian theories of value: it is no less circumstantial than the defenses taking the âlower groundâ.
The infinitary view does better. In particular, it blocks (2â). Hadynâs life involved at least some pleasure which was worth, on this view, times3 as much as a unit of oyster-life (which Crisp compares to âfloating very drunk in a warm bathâ). Thus, no matter how long the (Oyster) lives, it will never have a life as valuable as Hadynâs. So, at first pass, the infinitary view seems to achieve what Mill wants it to achieve.
Austerity
Under Millâs view (emphasis mine), âwhat makes one pleasure more valuable than anotherâ is the judgement of âa majority amongâ those who have enjoyed both. Crisp raises an objection (Austerity):
If I consistently apply the views of the panel in my decision-making, my life will be an austere one indeed. For their view is that reading philosophy is incommensurably more valuable than any lower pleasure. So it appears that my welfare will be promoted maximally if I stick at the philosophy for as long as possible.
However, his âwhole-lifeâ refinement (later, on the basis of this) is both unnecessary and implausible. Crisp finds unintuitive the apparent implication that reading all of Austenâs novels is better than reading all but one while having many varied lower pleasures. But if most competent judges share Crispâs intuition, there might be a higher pleasure which consists of something like the satisfaction of knowing that one is well-rounded. Sacrificing some higher pleasures for lower ones may be instrumental to this reflective pleasure. So a more careful glance shows that the simple infinitary view does not have this (Austerity) implication, rendering Crispâs refinement unnecessary.
Moreover, Crispâs revision is either silent on the value of particular acts, or else involves hybrid view on which quality matters only when considering a life overall. Both have clear downsides. The former doesnât seem fine-grained enough support a moral theory. The latter seems to imply that, say, the magical oyster which spends a day as Haydn before resuming oysterhood leads a more valuable life than the vast majority of people, or that a life which includes one paragraph of Austen is far better than one which includes no Austen (and is actually just as good as one which includes all of Austen). One might appeal at this point to reflective pleasures as outlined above, but this dissolves the original worry as well and leaves the view twisted into knots for no reason at all.4 So the infinitary view withstands (Austerity), and refinement is unnecessary.
Symmetry
However we interpret Millâs distinction, it faces another problem (Symmetry): Mill cannot in principle distinguish between higher pleasures and addictive lower pleasures. He writes:
Men lose their high aspirations as they lose their intellectual tastes, because they have not time or opportunity for indulging them; and they addict themselves to inferior pleasures, not because they deliberately prefer them, but because they are either the only ones to which they have access, or the only ones which they are any longer capable of enjoying.
Consider the case of apparently competent judges who have experienced Smartâs âelectrode operationâ (which directly stimulates the brainâs reward mechanisms â suppose, even, that this exploits mechanisms unique to humans). If Mill can undermine the competence of these judges by arguing that they have become incapable of enjoying the higher pleasures, these judges can do the same in reverse: someone who reads too much philosophy about âhuman dignityâ becomes unable to enjoy the higher pleasure of electrode operation. Similarly, they might adapt Millâs slogan: âbetter to be [a wirehead] dissatisfied than a [philosopher] satisfied. And if the [philosopher], or the pig, is of a different opinion, it is because they only know their own side of the question. The other party to the comparison knows both sides.â Note that these would not be eccentrics, either: presumably, the vast majority of competent judges would fall victim to the neurochemical addiction of electrode operation. So, at first pass, it seems difficult to raise an asymmetry consistent with Millâs views.
Smart attempts to address this worry by modifying Millâs view. What matters is not the judgements of competent judges, but those of people in general:
That is, for A to call B âhappyâ, A must be contented at the prospect of B being in his present state of mind and at the prospect of A himself, should the opportunity arise, enjoying that sort of state of mind.
Firstly, we may note that this is a departure from Millâs view. Millâs distinction relies upon the judgements of competent judges, and Smartâs departure seems so significant that even if it did successfully underwrite some distinction between higher and lower pleasures, it would not be Millâs distinction. Either way, though, Smartâs modification doesnât work. Consider R, a billionaire who indulges in a life of luxury and lower pleasures, and S, a philosopher who lives off stale bread and has no intimate relationships. It seems plausible that the vast majority of the human population (not to mention the sentient non-human population) might be more inclined to call R happy than to call S happy. Even if general opinion went the other way, it seems too contingent to ground poetry and philosophy as âhigherâ pleasures in principle, as Mill would like. So, Smartâs test is inadequate.
A further departure from Mill might be more plausible. Rather than a consensus of competent judges determining what would be best for everyone, whatâs best for each person might be determined by, say, âwhat [they] would prefer, now and in the various alternatives, if [they] knew all of the relevant facts about these alternativesâ5. Thus, pleasures are higher or lower for particular people, rather than higher or lower simpliciter. However, this view is now substantially different from Millâs own. So, Millâs method of drawing a distinction between higher and lower pleasures is not able to provide a defense of a utilitarian theory of value any more principled than other defenses which Mill critiqued as circumstantial.
To recap: Mill wants his distinction between higher and lower pleasures to provide a more principled defense of utilitarian theories of value against the degradingness objection. One feature of a more principled defense would be withstanding amended versions of the objection. However, the most textually-supported reading of Mill fails to do this for Crispâs (Oyster) case. If we amend our reading, as Crisp does, we are led to an infinitary reading which seems more principled at first pass. However, it falls to a more general objection: not the easily-met (Austerity) objection that Crisp raises, but rather a (Symmetry) objection which Smart raises but does not successfully address. While this objection may be answerable, doing so requires departing completely from Millâs distinction. So, Millâs own distinction is unable to achieve what he wants it to achieve.
An aside
Here is an aside on hedonism; I donât think itâs relevant to the essay title, but it seems relevant to the topic in general. That is, I assume it might come up in the tutorial, and so I wanted to note my thoughts (badly articulated, even compared to the above essay) here. The most relevant reference is Appendix I of Reasons and Persons, though Sumner (2009) has some related discussion about early theorists. Hedonism (in particular, preference hedonism) differs from desire-satisfaction (in particular, success theory) in that the former takes preferences only about âintrospectively discernible mental statesâ to matter, while the latter takes preferences about ourselves more generally. Both of these differ from objective list theory, on which values precede preferences: approximately, something can be good simpliciter, rather than just good for some particular person. Mill writes:
It may be questioned whether any one who has remained equally susceptible to both classes of pleasures, ever knowingly and calmly preferred the lower⊠the judgment of those who are qualified by knowledge of both, or, if they differ, that of the majority among them, must be admitted as final.
The first part shows the priority of pleasure over individual preference (and recall that pleasure is what matters to Mill). The second part shows that competent judges (even just a majority) determine what is valuable (i.e., pleasurable) in general. These are characteristic of an objective list theory. Mill runs preference hedonism and success theory together, but in the passage where he talks about being an âignoramusâ etc., he seems to speak of attributes which are not introspectively discernible. And unless we find (I grant there might be some, e.g., in Part IV, that Iâve overlooked) indication of a restriction toward sensations mattering, it seems as though Millâs test for higher-order pleasures also turns out in favor of desire-satisfaction over hedonism. In particular, competent judges likely prefer to have all their desires actually satisfied, not just ones about introspectively available sensations (e.g., âintelligent personâ vs. âfoolâ over âfeeling intelligentâ vs. âfeeling foolishâ). If this is right, Mill is actually furthest from hedonism!
References
- Bentham, Jeremy. The Rationale of Reward. England: Published by John and H. L. Hunt, 1825, 1825.
- Crisp, Roger. Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Mill on Utilitarianism. Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge, 2009.
- Mill, John Stuart. Utilitarianism. Luton: AUK Classics, 2014.
- Parfit, Derek. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986.
- Smart, J. J. C. (John Jamieson Carswell), and Bernard Williams. Utilitarianism: For and Against. Repr. with corrections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987.
Footnotes
-
I donât take it that Mill aimed to defend hedonism as such, only a rough approximation. So although itâs beyond the scope of my paper, Iâd like to argue/explore the very odd view that Millâs defense here is closest to a version of objective list theory, somewhat close to desire-satisfaction theory, and least close to hedonism! â©
-
Rather technically, for this to be plausible (e.g., unless any finite amount of the higher pleasure is just as good as any other finite amount), experiences must be compared by ordinal value rather than cardinal value. But cf. Crispâs âwhole-lifeâ view, for which cardinals in this sense may be sufficient and even necessary. He uses the term âcardinalâ differently (closer to economics than set theory), but thatâs far beyond my focus here. â©
-
Here âÏâ means, as usual, the first non-zero limit ordinal: the smallest number greater than all the natural numbers. â©
-
This is similar to Global versions of e.g. Success Theory (see Parfit), but (a) is motivated quite differently and (b) includes (is about) the baggage of Millâs distinction. â©
-
This is Parfitâs description of âGlobal Success Theoryâ. â©